Keyboard Shortcuts?

×
  • Next step
  • Previous step
  • Skip this slide
  • Previous slide
  • mShow slide thumbnails
  • nShow notes
  • hShow handout latex source
  • NShow talk notes latex source
\def \ititle {06: Decision Theory and Habitual Processes}
 
\begin{center}
 
{\Large
 
\textbf{\ititle}
 
}
 
 
 
\iemail %
 
\end{center}
 
 
 
\section{Decision Theory}
 
‘we should think of meanings and beliefs as interrelated constructs of a single theory just as we already view subjective values and probabilities as interrelated constructs of decision theory’
\citep[p.~146]{Davidson:1974gh}
 
 
 
\section{Game Theory}
 
‘we wish to find the mathematically complete principles which define “rational behavior” for the participants in a social economy, and to derive from them the general characteristics of that behavior’
\citep[p.~31]{neumann:1953_theory}
 
‘we wish to find the mathematically complete principles which define “rational behavior” for the participants in a social economy, and to derive from them the general characteristics of that behavior’
\citep[p.~31]{neumann:1953_theory}
 
A nash equilibrium for a game
is a profile of actions
from which no agent can unilaterally profitably deviate
 
Decision Theory is about how individuals decide which of several available actions to perform \citep[textbook:][]{Jeffrey:1983oe}. Game Theory is a development which focusses on how interacting individuals select actions when which outcome one individuals’s action brings about depends on how another acts.
 
 
 
\section{Descision Theory Is Agnostic about Processes}
 
On explanation: ‘Many events and outcomes prompt us to ask: Why did that happen? [...] For example, cutthroat competition in business is the result of the rivals being trapped in a prisoners’ dilemma’
\citep[p.~36]{dixit:2014_games}.
 
\begin{enumerate} \item Applications of game theory range from interactions between microbial populations to interactions between countries. \item The explanations are of the same type in every case. \item The underlying processes probably differ. \item Therefore, game theory is agnostic about processes. \end{enumerate}
 
 
 
\section{Processes: Habitual vs Instrumental}
 
What kinds of processes in individual animals guide actions?
 
\emph{Thorndyke’s Law of Effect}:
‘The presenta­tion of an effective [=rewarding] outcome following an action [...] rein­forces
a connection between the stimuli present when the action is per­formed and the action itself
so that subsequent presentations of these stimuli elicit the [...] action as a response’
\citep[p.48]{Dickinson:1994sm}
 
 
 
\section{A Puzzle about Action}
 
‘the laboratory rat fits the teleological [instrumental] model; performance of this particular instrumental behaviour really does seem to be controlled byknowledge about the relation between the action and the goal’
\citep[p.~72]{Dickinson:1985qp}
 
‘we did not conclude that all such responding was of this form.
Indeed, we observed some residual responding during the post-re-valuation test that appeared to be impervious to outcome devaluation and therefore autonomous of the current incentive value,
and we speculated that this responding was habitual
and established by a process akin to the stimulus-response (S-R)/reinforcement mechanism embodied in Thorndike’s classic Law of Effect (Thorndike, 1911).
\citep[p.~179]{dickinson:2016_instrumental}
 
The puzzle: \begin{enumerate} \item If the action is habitual, why is it modulated by devaulation? \item If the action is instrumental, why does it still occur (albeit less frequently) after devaluation? \end{enumerate}
 
 
 
\section{A Dual-Process Theory of Action}
 
some actions are ‘controlled by two dissociable processes: a goal-directed [instrumental] and an habitual process’
\citep{Dickinson:1985qp,dickinson:2016_instrumental}
 
‘[instumental] and habitual control have been doubly dissociated in two brain regions.
 
In the PFC, lesions of the prelimbic and infralimbic areas disrupt goal-directed [instrumental] and habitual behavior, respectively ...
 
These dissociations suggest that different neural circuits mediate the two forms of control’
\citep[p~184]{dickinson:2016_instrumental}
 
 
 
\section{Stress}
 
‘instrumental behavior itself involves two systems, the goal-directed and the habitual’
\citep[p.~12]{dickinson:2018_actions}
 
‘once we accept that there are complex and subtle non-intentional processes, such as those mediating basic goal-approach and the adjustment to changes in motivational state, that can mimic true intentional control in many situations, we can understand why the propensity to perceive actions as intentional may have developed. Given that
 
either there is nothing in the stimulus input per se to distinguish intentional from non-intentional behaviour
 
or that
 
such a discrimination yields little of consequence in most situations,
 
it may well pay the perceiver to treat both classes of behaviour as intentional in predicting the subsequent course of events’
\citep[p.~102]{heyes:1990_intentionality}.
 
 
 
\section{Is Decision Theory Really Agnostic about Processes?}
 
 
 
\section{Construals of Decision Theory}
 
My proposal: \begin{quote} Decision Theory (like Game Theory) specifies a model of action. Models can be construed in several different ways. Decision Theory says nothing about how the model should be construed. \end{quote} Alternatives exist. For instance, \citet{binmore:1994_playing} claims the axioms of game theory are tautologies; on his story, the games are the models.
 
‘Theories, as they are usually understood by philosophers, make claims about the world [...]
 
Models, in my sense, do not themselves say anything about the world.
 
Models are structures that can be used by scientists to say various different things about the world,
 
by means of commentaries that accompany models but are distinct from them’
\citep[p.~4]{godfrey-smith:2005_folk}.
 
‘Two scientists can use the same model to help with the same target system while having quite different views of how the model might be representing the target system. I will describe this situation by saying that the two scientists have different construals of the model’
\citep[p.~4]{godfrey-smith:2005_folk}
 
‘one scientist might [construe] some model simply as an input-output device, as a predictive tool.
 
Another might [construe] the same model as a faithful map of the inner workings of the target system’
\citep[p.~4]{godfrey-smith:2005_folk}
 
‘Basic facility with the folk-psychological model does not require using a particular construal of it. Many construals are possible.
 
And it is also possible to have facility with the model, and have a sense of which target systems are appropriate for it, while not having much of a construal at all
\citep[p.~5]{godfrey-smith:2005_folk}.
 
 
 
\section{Training Effects}
 

Click here and press the right key for the next slide (or swipe left)

\title {Philosophical Psychology \\ 06: Decision Theory and Habitual Processes}
 
\maketitle
 
\section{Decision Theory}
 
\section{Decision Theory}
How do rational agents decide which of several available actions to perform?
 
\section{Game Theory}
 
\section{Game Theory}
A game is ‘any interaction between agents that is governed by a set of rules specifying the possible moves for each participant and a set of outcomes for each possible combination of moves’ (Hargreaves and Varoufakis, 2004 p. 3)
 
\section{Descision Theory Is Agnostic about Processes}
 
\section{Descision Theory Is Agnostic about Processes}
You might be tempted to interpret decision theory as a description of how people reason. Is any such interpretation obligatory? Observation of how decision theory is applied supports the conclusion that decision theory is agnostic about processes.
 
\section{Processes: Habitual vs Instrumental}
 
\section{Processes: Habitual vs Instrumental}
What kinds of processes in individual animals guide actions? Research in animal learning enables us to distinguish habitual and instrumental processes (see Dickinson, 1985).
 
\section{A Puzzle about Action}
 
\section{A Puzzle about Action}
A rat has been given food contingent on its pressing a level. When it presses the lever, is its action habitual or instrumental? (This part also explains devaluation.)
 
\section{A Dual-Process Theory of Action}
 
\section{A Dual-Process Theory of Action}
Actions are neither habitual or instrumental. Actions are controlled by two or more distinct kinds of process, one instrumental and the other habitual.
 
\section{Stress}
 
\section{Stress}
When stressed, your preferences matter less: habits dominate (Schwabe & Wolf, 2010).
 
\section{Is Decision Theory Really Agnostic about Processes?}
 
\section{Is Decision Theory Really Agnostic about Processes?}
The range of applications of decision theory indicates that it must be agnostic about processes. But Dickinson’s instrumental process is characterised by appeal to Decision Theory. How can the apparent tension between these facts be resolved?
 
\section{Construals of Decision Theory}
 
\section{Construals of Decision Theory}
Decision Theory specifies a model of action. Models can be construed in several different ways. Decision Theory says nothing about how the model should be construed.
 
\section{Training Effects}
 
\section{Training Effects}
Whether you learn about the effects of an action can influence whether that action becomes dominated by instrumental or habitual processes (Klossek et al, 2011)).